Until
18th century, torturing criminal was grisly public spectacle even in developed
countries. For instance, a man who attempted to the king was drawn and
quartered in a public execution.
The
form of punishment experienced notable changes from 18th to 19th century in
Europe. First, the punishment became no longer public spectacle and the
executioners tried to abbreviate pain of criminals (in a case, criminals are
injected with tranquilizers). The change implies a whole new morality
concerning the act of punishment. Second, the leniency was accompanied by the
change of objectives in punishment. The punishment began to be designed to
strike the soul rather than the body.
It is
easy to explain the change simply as the expansion of humanity or the development
of the human sciences, but that approach faces risk in missing the important
perspectives, argued Michel Foucault, a French philosopher, known as the
representative structuralism thinker.
In his
book, “Discipline and Punish”, he analyzed the history of the modern spirit and
of a new power to judge, through the study of history of punishments and
prisons.
Four rules in studying history of
punishment
Foucault
suggested four general rules in studying the history of punishments to see it
from much broader perspective, such that we can reach to the profound
understanding of the social change. I believe the methodology is applicable to
all the related studies:
First,
he regarded punishment as a complex social function. He did not concentrate on the
study of the punitive mechanisms on their repressive effects alone, but
situated them in a whole series of their possible positive effects, even if
these seem marginal at first sight.
Second,
he regarded punishment as a political tactics. He analyzed punitive methods not
simply as consequences of legislation, but as techniques possessing their own
specificity in the more general field of other ways of exercising power.
Third,
he made the “technology of power” the very principle both of the humanization
of the penal system and of the knowledge of man. He thought the technology of
power is behind both the history of penal law and the history of human
sciences. He said:
“We
should admit rather that power produces knowledge; that power and knowledge
directly imply one another; that there is no power relation without the
correlative constitution of a field of knowledge, nor any knowledge that does
not presuppose and constitute at the same time power relations. These
‘power-knowledge relations’ are to be analyzed, therefore, not on the basis of
a subject of knowledge who is or is not free in relation to the power system,
but, on the contrary, the subject who knows, the objects to be known and the
modalities of knowledge must be regarded as so many effects of these fundamental
implications of power-knowledge and their historical transformations.” (page
27-28)
Fourth,
he studied the metamorphosis of punitive methods on the basis of a political
technology of the body which might be read a common history of power relations
and object relations. In that way, he regarded the change of penal leniency as
one of the power techniques.
Power shift behind the change in
punishments
Foucault
thought that the public execution is to be understood not only as a judicial
but also as a political ritual; more precisely, he thought that the execution
is the representation of power, saying: “The reform of criminal law must be
read as a strategy for the rearrangement of the power to punish. … The new
juridical theory of penalty corresponds in fact to a new ‘political economy’ of
the power to punish.”
The
cruel (and costly) tortures reflected the absolute power of monarchy at that
time. The style of tortures changed, essentially because of the power shift
from monarchs to the bourgeoisie. After the Revolution, new power needed to
constitute a new economy and a new technology of the power to punish, and the
rise of the social contract theory can be understood through this context.
The
penalty changed accordingly. After the Revolution, the main penalty became
imprisonment, i.e. the penalty to deprive the criminals of freedom, which is
the central value in the Revolution. The characteristics of the penalty
underwent the following changes:
- Unarbitrary
application and public acceptance of rules
- More
focus on incentivizing people not to commit crimes
-
Designed to emphasize rules rather than sovereign powers
He
summarizes his idea as follows:
“In
the late eighteenth century, one is confronted by three ways of organizing the
power to punish. The first is the one that was still functioning and which was
based on the old monarchical law. The other two both refer to a preventive,
utilitarian, corrective conception of a right to punish that belongs to society
as a whole; but they are very different from one another at the level of the
mechanisms they envisage. Broadly speaking, one might say that, in monarchical
law, punishment is a ceremonial of sovereignty; it uses the ritual marks of the
vengeance (retaliation) that it applies to the body of the condemned man; and
it deploys before the eyes of the spectators an effect of terror as intense as
it is discontinuous, irregular and always above its own laws, the physical
presence of the sovereign and of his power. The reforming jurists, on the other
hand, saw punishment as a procedure for requalifying individuals as subjects,
as juridical subjects; it uses not marks, but signs, coded sets of
representations, which would be given the most rapid circulation and the most
general acceptance possible by citizens witnessing the scene of punishment. “
(P130)
Individualism and the rise of discipline
The
next thing Foucault analyzed is the discipline. He pointed out the discipline
experienced major change at the same when punishments became lenient. Discipline
is like a substructure of the social body. While the upper structure is
established by politicians and philosophers, disciplines are often made by
soldiers in army, teachers in schools, doctors in hospitals, etc. Foucault
meticulously looked into how discipline worked to people, by saying that
discipline is political anatomy of detail, quoting Marshal de Saxe: “Although
those who concern themselves with details are regarded as folk of limited
intelligence, it seems to me that this part is essential, because it is the
foundation, and it is impossible to erect any building or establish any method
without understanding its principles.”
Discipline
is composed of three factors. The first is observation - especially the
apparatus that makes it possible to see everything constantly. The ultimate
form of observation apparatus is that of panopticons. The second is a small
penal mechanism, the informal rule which is intrinsic to the group and requires
no judicial system; the penal mechanism works to correct individuals’ behavior.
The third is examination, which combines the techniques of observation and the
group’s internal rules.
Foucault
argued that the discipline marked the moment when the political individualism
takes place. The essence of discipline is that it “makes” individuals; it is
the specific technique of a power that regards individuals both as objects and
as instruments of its exercise. As the society put much importance of
individuals, power becomes more anonymous and more functional, those on whom
discipline is exercised tend to be more strongly individualized. As discipline
worked to reduce the “gap” from the ideal status, after the rise of discipline,
the child, the patient, the madman and the delinquent became more
individualized than the adult, the healthy man, the normal and the
non-delinquent man.
The birth of prison
Although
prisons existed before the modern civil revolution, the penalty of detention (deprivation
of liberty) was a new thing, Foucault argued.
As
Baltard said, prisons are “complete and austere institutions”; prisons are the
perfect disciplinary institutions in that it assumes responsibility of all
aspects of the individuals, his physical training, his aptitude to work, his
everyday conduct, his moral attitude, his state of mind, etc. (page 235) The
penitentiary technique and the delinquent of prisons are a technological
ensemble that forms and fragments the object to which it applies its
instruments. In that sense, the prison is the place where the power to punish
organizes a field of objectivity in which punishment will be able to function
open as treatment and the sentence will be inscribed among the discourses of
knowledge. Foucault thought that the characteristics of prisons are the reason
why justice adopted a prison.
Remarks
This
is an outstanding book. Foucault tells us how to look through the things. As
Marx once said a good reflects everything of capitalism society, discipline and
punishment played the same role, explaining social changes. If we just look at
phenomena, we may miss the larger change (power shift in his terminology) that
fundamentally drives all the changes. As Foucault showed in this book, the
importance thing is to (1) look through details of the phenomena and (2) relate
the phenomena to the other social changes. This analysis requires extensive
knowledge in many fields, and this reminds us of learning various topics.
Reference:
Michel
Foucault, “Discipline & Punish: The Birth of the Prison”, Vintage, 1995
No comments:
Post a Comment